answersLogoWhite

0


Best Answer

> They didnt know better

Prior to there invention of the microscope around 1600, there were no instruments capable of detecting single-cell organisms. Francisco Redi's experiments, published in 1668, are considered the first steps in refuting spontaneous generation.

User Avatar

Wiki User

13y ago
This answer is:
User Avatar
More answers
User Avatar

Wiki User

11y ago

They didn't know how else they appeared and thought that humans were the only organisms that mated.

  • Open in Google Docs Viewer
  • Open link in new tab
  • Open link in new window
  • Open link in new incognito window
  • Download file
  • Copy link address
  • Edit PDF File on PDFescape.com
This answer is:
User Avatar

User Avatar

Wiki User

12y ago

Needham believed in spontaneous generation

This answer is:
User Avatar

User Avatar

Wiki User

14y ago

beacause they saw the meat had nonliving things on it

This answer is:
User Avatar

User Avatar

Wiki User

11y ago

Spontaneous generation theory allowed people to believe that living organisms (microorganism) could arise or develop from non-living matter.

This answer is:
User Avatar

User Avatar

Wiki User

11y ago

i that there is no "parent"

This answer is:
User Avatar

Add your answer:

Earn +20 pts
Q: Why did the spontaneous generation hypothesis seem logical at the time?
Write your answer...
Submit
Still have questions?
magnify glass
imp
Continue Learning about Natural Sciences

How does sample size affect your level of confidence in accepting a hypothesis?

The larger the sample size the more confident you can be that the data you have collected is representative of what would happen on a larger scale. So if your results seem to prove your hypothesis right then the larger you sample size the more confident you can be in accepting your hypothesis.


Does a hypothesis test ever prove the null hypothesis?

The traditional view that one cannot prove the null hypothesis by a statistical analysis is a consequence of Ronald Fisher's structuring of the problem of probabilistic inference. Fisher argued that if one wanted to determine whether an experimental manipulation (e.g., a drug treatment or a treatment of some crop land) had an effect (on e.g., recovery rate or crop yield), one should compute the probability that one would obtain an effect (that is, a difference in the means of two samples, a control sample, and an experimental sample) as big or bigger than the one in fact obtained if both samples were in fact drawn from the same distribution (that is, if there were in fact no effect). In other words, how likely is it that one would see an effect that big or bigger by chance? If this probability is sufficiently low (say, less than one chance in 20), then one is justified in concluding that what one did had an effect (or that there was a difference in the average values in the populations that one drew the two samples from). Thus, if the difference in the means of the two samples was sufficiently greater than expected by chance, then one was justified in concluding that something more than chance was at work. This way of framing the problem has come to be called Null Hypothesis Significance Testing (NHST, for short). In this formulation, you cannot prove the null hypothesis, because failing to reject it is not the same as accepting it--anymore than a verdict of "not proven" is the same as a verdict of "not guilty." Thus, if you think this is the right way to formulate the problem of probabilistic inference, then you cannot prove the null. But this way of formulating the problem flies in the face of common sense. We all draw a strong and clear distinction between "not proven" and "not guilty." In this formulation, the only possible verdict as regards the null hypothesis is "not proven." This would perhaps be okay if null hypotheses were of no scientific or practical importance. But, in fact, they are of profound scientific and practical importance. The conservation laws, which are at the foundation of modern physics, are null hypotheses; they all assert that "under no circumstance does this change." And, for most people it matters whether a generic drug costing 1/10 the cost of a brand drug really has "the same effect" as the brand drug or just "has not been proven to have a different effect." If you frame it in the latter way, then many more people will opt to pay the additional cost than if you say that "the evidence shows that the effects of the generic drug and the brand drug do not differ" (a null hypothesis). Moreover, and this is more technical, the traditional formulation violates basic mathematical/logical considerations. One of these is consistency: a rational treatment of the evidence for and against any hypothesis should have the property that as the number of observations "goes to infinity" (becomes arbitrarily large), then the probability of drawing the correct conclusion should go to 1. But, under the NHST formulation, when the null hypothesis is true, the probability of rejecting it remains .05 or .01 (whatever one regards at the crucial degree of improbability) no matter how many observations there are. Another curious aspect of the traditional formulation is that it licenses concluding the one's own (non-null) hypothesis is correct because the null hypothesis appears to fail, even though one's own hypothesis is never tested against the data, whereas the null hypothesis is. This is a little bit like concluding that one could oneself climb a formidable mountain just because someone else has failed to climb it. Fairness would seem to require that one's own hypothesis, whatever it may be, should undergo the same test that the null hypothesis has undergone. At a somewhat simpler level, How can a statistical method for drawing conclusions be valid if it prohibits ever drawing a conclusion in favor of some hypotheses (null hypotheses) that are of fundamental scientific and practical importance? There is an alternative to the NHST formulation of the problem of probabilistic inference that dates back to the work of the Reverend Thomas Bayes in the 18th century. In the Bayesian formulation, both the null hypothesis and one or more alternatives to it are tested against the data. In this formulation, each of the hypotheses places a bet on where the data from the experimental treatment (or the other condition of observation) will fall. The hypothesis that does the best job of anticipating where the data in fact fall obtains the greatest odds of being correct (or, at least, more valid than the alternatives to it that have been proposed). In this formulation, it is perfectly possible for the null hypothesis to be the odds on favorite. In other words, in this conception of how to do probabilistic inference, it is possible to prove the null in the sense that the null may have arbitrarily greater odds as against any of the proposed alternative to it. Thus, in this formulation, the null is no different than any other hypothesis. This approach to the problem of probabilistic inference has gained considerable currency in recent years. According to its advocates, it is the only "normative" (mathematically correct) formulation, because, among other things, it does not prohibit any hypothesis from being accepted, and because it is consistent: as the data (number of observations) become arbitrarily large, the odds that the true hypothesis will be accepted increase toward infinity, regardless of whether the true hypothesis is the null hypothesis or an alternative to it. In short, the Bayesian formulation places the null hypothesis on the same footing as any other hypothesis, so it is just as susceptible of proof as any other hypothesis.


Why are leonids showers called leonid showers?

The radiant - the direction they seem to come from - is in the constellation of the lion.The radiant - the direction they seem to come from - is in the constellation of the lion.The radiant - the direction they seem to come from - is in the constellation of the lion.The radiant - the direction they seem to come from - is in the constellation of the lion.


Why do they seem to disappear?

plants and animals that die seem to disappear because it causes danger for the person or children


What makes a comet seem larger than the sun?

comets can sometimes seem larger than the sun because they are closer to the earth

Related questions

What color is a bluegill?

It would seem logical that at least part of it is blue.


What details in the interlopers make its surprise ending seem logical?

Mrs.Kubltitz knows


Heating air only makes it hotter?

That would seem to be a logical truth.


What is a supporting hypothesis?

A well-supported hypothesis is a theory that appears to have a lot of evidence behind it. This evidence helps to make it seem likely that the hypothesis is true, but it is still just a theory until it has been proven.


What hypothesis by Alfred Wegener explains why continents seem to fit together?

plate tectonics


What hypothesis by Alfred wegener explains why continents seem to fit togethere?

Alfred Wegener proposed the theory of continental drift, suggesting that continents were once joined together in a single supercontinent called Pangaea. Over time, the supercontinent broke apart and the continents drifted to their current positions, explaining why they seem to fit together like pieces of a puzzle.


What comes after one and a half cup?

2 cups would seem logical.


Has substance abuse increased with this generation?

This generation is the largest generation yet. It would seem that the substance abuse has also increased but percentage wise it is still the same at about 25%.


What does PHECOA mean in science?

Purpose Hypothesis Experiment Conclusion and I can't seem to remember O and A


Does the way you dress reflects if you are artistically creative or not?

of course not! you could wear the same clothes everyday and seem artistic if you are spontaneous and act the part!


Why is logical reasoning problematic in the field of ethics?

One apparent obstacle to this process is that logical reasoning, at least at first glance, does not seem to lead different people to the same ethical conclusions and answers.


Which best explains the term imaginative leap?

A way of making emotional sense out of of ideas that might not seem logical