answersLogoWhite

0

What is recursive epistemology?

Updated: 10/26/2022
User Avatar

Wiki User

11y ago

Best Answer
First and Second-Order (Recursive) EpistemologiesGregory Bateson famously said that we "cannot claim to have no epistemology. Those who so claim have nothing but a bad epistemology." Bateson is calling for self-reflection in our epistemology. He wants it to be recursive, so that in our production of knowledge we do not delude ourselves into thinking that the means of production is independent of what is produced. The consequences of lacking a self-reflexive epistemology are dire, leading to real practical and ethical dilemmas. The structure of the sequence often goes something like this:

· Knowledge is produced on the basis of a non-reflexive epistemology (Bateson's "bad" epistemology).

· The knowledge produced is thus assumed to be "objective" and "true" (i.e. independent of the means of its production; ignorant of its genesis).

· This tends to have a psychologically limiting effect with respect to alternative knowledge and especially alternative modes of knowledge production. One's viewpoint becomes ossified.

· The unreflective assumption of the "truth" of the knowledge becomes justification for its projection, often forcefully, onto other people and processes in the environments surrounding the knower. A sense of conviction that the world is "like this" leads to inflexible protocols in our institutions and in our modes of interaction with others. In other words, outer processes are also ossified; they become sclerotic.

Calibration and Self-Calibration.But what does it mean to have a self-reflexive epistemology? The difference between the two types of epistemologies, non-self-relfexive and self-reflexive, can be described by the first and second order difference. A non-self-reflexive epistemology is a first-order epistemology, a process of creating knowledge that operates in a linear fashion. The knowledge it generates is not explicitly connected to the process of its generation, and thus does not act as a potential corrective to its mode of production. Epistemology is a tool for knowing; but with a non-self-reflexive epistemology, the tool's operation does not change the tool, so that no matter what job it is called to do, it re-instances any new creations in the manner and style of its past processes-regardless of what might be new in the situation it encounters. The kind of newness that comes from a linear epistemology is innovative, but not radical. It is well-suited to the kinds of knowledge domains that work towards technical, but not paradigmatic, advances.

To use a term from cybernetics, a linear epistemology is not open to calibration. But this lack of openness to calibration is often not simply passive, but active: attempts at calibration are often either discarded or met with increasing rigidity, with a sort of "doubling-down" on the knowledge already produced by the epistemology, and an increasing unwillingness to change the process by which knowledge is produced. We could therefore describe this kind of epistemology as willfully ignorant. This can actually be quite beneficial in producing new knowledge (within the parameters already accepted by the epistemology), because it minimizes the recursive complexity and is more amenable to simplification. Reductionisms of all types, where all phenomena, regardless of their complexity, are explained only in terms of more simple (and often more abstract) entities, are linear epistemologies. Said differently, a linear epistemology allows one to ignore second-order alternatives. Most of modern scientific thinking rests on the back of linear epistemology, to which it is well-suited.

On the other hand, a self-reflexive epistemology is a second-order epistemology (see Table 1 below for a comparison of qualities). The process allows itself to be changed by the content it produces. It is thus an open epistemology that operates on the basis of a recursion between process and content. It is open to calibration, and not simply in a passive way, but actively: it seeks calibration of its own processes through an active monitoring of what it is generating. Whereas a linear epistemology tends to minimize calibrative influences (changes in the way it operates at a second-order level), a recursive epistemology actively embodies them at its heart; it is not merely open to calibration, but is self-calbrative. The linking of process and content in this recursive way is akin to the creation of a new type of sensitivity; we can metaphorically say that operating with a recursive epistemology is the development of a new type of higher sense-organ for a knowing system. This is another way of saying that what a system distinguishes distinguishes its distinguishing. Recursive epistemology is open to self-revision not only at the content level (which is also true of linear epistemologies, although there may still be a difference in their relative inertia to this change), but also at the process level. This means that the kind of newness it can potentially yield includes radical, as well as technical shifts. Radical shifts restructure the further possibilities that are available to the knowing system; they are paradigmatic shifts.

What is important to consider is that the recursion between knowledge and knowing (between content and process) actually applies to allepistemologies, even first-order epistemologies. It is simply that in the case of a first-order epistemology, the epistemology is not systemically inclusive of this fact; we could say that it is not sensitive to its own sensitivity. A second-order epistemology is sensitive to its sensitivities: it includes processes whose content is other processes. The most tightly recursive epistemologies have processes whose content is itself.

The Unknown and Unknowing.Every epistemology has its boundary, a place where it meets a kind of threshold of what it can so far distinguish to itself. Here again we have a first and second-order difference. The first-order level to this threshold is the possible content that could be revealed there, if only our knowing could continue across the threshold. This is the unknown, as a content. The second-order level to the threshold is the ongoing activity of the unknowing.

A first-order epistemology meets its boundary only by virtue of the loss of what is seen as its potential content. The unknown is assumed to be a specific content that is just like the known in every way except that has yet to be brought to light, discovered, or found. These metaphors work from the assumption that knowledge is somehow waiting "out there" to be had, and the protocols for knowledge production are thus geared towards the transformation of the unknown into the known, often with forceful manipulation and through maximization of control procedures. The unknown is precisely what needs to be minimized, and processes that generate unknowing are therefore seen as barriers to further knowing, leading only to confusion and unclarity. The unknown is valued only negatively, as the not-yet-known. The not-yet-known is pulled through from the other side of the threshold and brought "down" to re-instance the same reality that the epistemology already operates within, as further proof of its existence. The first-order epistemology focuses on the content of what it produces, and derives from this content the very justification for its truth; it invests its validity in its facts.

A second-order epistemology meets its boundary also by virtue of what is not known, but in addition it values the unknowing as an active and potentially transformative process. What for the first-order epistemology is only a potential new content is for the second-order epistemology a potential new way of being. This is a higher-order content, and is not simply "out there" to be discovered but must be enacted to exist; it must be brought into being. The unknowing is thus taken to be an invitation, a doorway, and instead of taking the unknown and making it known through the same epistemological patterns, it opens the door to more unknowing. Enacting a second-order epistemology is to allow one's way of knowing to change, not just the content of what is known. Unknowing is thus valued as a transformative agent, as a source of not only new knowledge but new ways of living forward. For a second-order epistemology, unknowing is a feature to be actively worked with, even developed, rather than a bug to be squashed. Said another way, a linear epistemology does not know that it does not know, while a recursive epistemology does, and makes of this something new of itself. The active incorporation of processes that yield states of unknowing is a primary way that a recursive epistemology self-calibrates.

Table 1. A comparison of the qualities of linear and recursive epistemologies.

Linear Episetmology

Recursive Epistemology

Non-self-reflexive

Self-reflexive

First-order

Second-order

Process kept independent of content

Process changes in response to content

Truth is objective and "out there"

Truth is a way of relating process and content

Content-focused

Process-focused

Validation reflected by its content

Validation as ongoing content-process recursions

Tends toward technical innovation

Can yield paradigmatic shifts

Knowledge produced as "pieces"

Knowledge produced as "wholes"

Unknown as potentially known content

Unknowing as potentially

transformative process

Observer split from environment

Observer and environment are mutually constituted in one process

User Avatar

Wiki User

11y ago
This answer is:
User Avatar

Add your answer:

Earn +20 pts
Q: What is recursive epistemology?
Write your answer...
Submit
Still have questions?
magnify glass
imp
Related questions

What are the principal issues in epistemology?

Epistemology is the science about how we gather knowledge


What is recursive association?

a recursive association - as a aggregation is a special form of association, so recursive aggregation can be called as recursive association ... AKASH SISODIYA ......IT ...


Where can one learn more about epistemology?

One can learn more about epistemology by reading books by prominent philosophers in the field, taking university courses on the topic, attending lectures or conferences, and engaging in discussions with experts in philosophy. Online resources such as academic journals and websites dedicated to philosophy can also be helpful for gaining a deeper understanding of epistemology.


What is the difference between ontology and epistemology?

ontology is what you can know epistemology is how you can know it


When was Social Epistemology - journal - created?

Social Epistemology - journal - was created in 1987.


When was Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology created?

Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology was created in 1979.


How many pages does Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology have?

Introduction to Objectivist Epistemology has 164 pages.


Are all recursive programs non recursive?

None of them is, obviously.


What does the word recursive mean?

Something that is recursive is something that repeats.


What is the definition of recursive?

The term recursive refers to the recurrence or repetition.


What is set difference between recursive and recursively enumerable but not recursive?

All recursive Languages are recursively enumerable. But not all the recursively enumerable languages are recursive. It is just like NP complete.


What is the meaning of dual epistemology?

Dual epistemology refers to the concept of having two distinct ways of knowing or understanding the world. It suggests that there are multiple valid ways of acquiring knowledge, such as through empirical evidence and subjective experience, and that these can complement each other in the pursuit of truth or understanding.